37 pages • 1 hour read
Ronald WrightA modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.
In 1890 the French painter and writer Gauguin left Paris for the tropics, longing to find “primordial man” (1). After receiving word of his daughter’s death, he painted a new work, titled D'où Venons Nous? Que Sommes Nous? Où Allons Nous? (Where do we come from? What are we? Where are we going?) In this book, Wright will try to answer Gauguin’s third question by first answering the other two. This is a necessary undertaking, as humans today cannot afford to risk the same mistakes we have made in the past. Because of our globalized reality and shrinking renewable resources, “the vessel we are now aboard [i.e. our current civilization] is not merely the biggest of all time; it is also the only one left” (3).
Belief in the Victorian ideal of progress, the idea that history continually moves towards improvement, has been strong since the Scientific Revolution. However, this idea is a “myth” (4) just like all others—a “map by which cultures navigate through time” (4). Although progress has served civilization well, it also possesses “an internal logic that can lead beyond reason into catastrophe” (5). Claims that Western capitalism is the highest zenith of civilizational development, despite its clear ecological and cultural consequences, are examples of delusions of progress. The atomic bomb is another example of the destructive capabilities scientific progress can reach. Belief that progress is innately good is not just a problem of the modern era—historical societies have also collapsed because of excessive use of their resources or technological advancements. Progress’s capability of exceeding its own limits is the idea of the progress trap (6).
Throughout the Paleolithic (c. 3mya-12kya) the pace of human progress was slow. People began using fire around 500,000 years ago, and this technological advancement brought about the first population spike. Fire revolutionized our ability to survive our landscape, allowing cooking, land-clearing, and a way to keep predators at bay.
Neanderthals evolved about 130,000 years ago and went extinct roughly 30,000 years ago. Science was initially unsure how to classify the Neanderthal, but today we appreciate that the Neanderthal was a cognitively complex subspecies of the homo genus which may have interbred with Cro-Magnons (a now defunct term Wright uses to denote the earliest anatomically modern humans). Though the two species have anatomical differences, Neanderthal and Cro-Magnon material culture “was identical over a span of more than 50,000 years…. [which is] strong evidence that the two groups had very similar mental and linguistic capacities” (21).
40,000 years ago, Cro-Magnons began to overtake the colder regions of Europe where the heavier-set Neanderthal thrived. This coincided with climactic changes, which were difficult for Neanderthals to deal with, as they lived in more sedentary hunter-gatherer groups than the nomadic Cro-Magnons. Over the next 10,000 years, Neanderthals and Cro-Magnons seem to have been in competition. At this time “new tools and weapons appeared, new clothing and rituals, and the beginnings of cave painting” (24). Wright argues such innovations were sparked by this conflict, which may have been history’s first recorded genocide. William Golding proposes a similar narrative in The Inheritors, a novel about fictional early humanoids in competition. Both the book and early human history suggest modern humans inherit a history of incredible violence, as well a capacity to innovate and thereby “tamper… with our destiny” (27) for our very earliest ancestors.
Of the 5 Chapters of A Short History of Progress, Chapter 1 is the best example of how Wright fuses art and literary criticism, contemporary history, and archaeology to make composite arguments about themes in human civilization. This is exemplified well in Wright’s brief biography of Gauguin transforming into a cultural history of Victorian thought, which then shifts into archaeological considerations of early humans before closing with reflections on a novel. This sweeping nature of the text’s relationship to both history and genre helps us understand why Wright dubs it a "short [i.e. compressed, general] history," though we must acknowledge it also sometimes leads to relatively lax or rushed interpretations of scientific data, such as in Wright’s proposition of Cro-Magnon-on-Neanderthal genocide.
Early on in the chapter, Wright gives us the reasoning behind the chapter's title. “Gauguin’s Questions” refers to the three questions of Gaugin’s painting: Where do we come from? What are we? Where are we going? In asking these questions, Wright employs the culturally inquisitive painter Gauguin as a foil of himself and allows Gauguin’s questions to become the seminal questions of Wright’s own book. Wright’s use of Gauguin again exemplifies how the author can use individuals, their art, and other cultural products as artefacts through which to examine cultural conditions, a standard archaeological framework enriched by Wright’s diverse academic background.
Wright provides a careful examination of the “Victorian ideal of progress” (3) at the outset of this chapter, which Wright defines through a quotation of Sidney Pollard: “the assumption that a pattern of change exists in the history of mankind… that It consists of irreversible changes in one direction only, and that this direction is towards improvement” (3). Wright argues that the idea of progress as essentially good is a foundational “myth” (4) of our culture, one that we can either ascribe to Victorian elitism or to human’s natural urge to innovate, improve, and excel. This concept of progress is a trap that leads us to all the abuses of science and technology that currently damage our environments and societies. This history of the Victorian ideal of progress, therefore, is deeply tied to Wright’s argument that we must examine the histories of ancient cultures—where do we come from—to come to understand our nature—what are we—in order to predict our future—where we are going? As Wright writes, “If we see clearly what we are and what we have done we can recognize human behaviour that persists through many times and cultures. Knowing this can tell us what we are likely to do, where we are likely to go from here” (2).
Wright also provides a history of evolutionary science earlier in this chapter as intertwined with the Victorian ideal (pages 11-12). Discussion of this history will lead to Wright’s own treatise on early human evolution, and it also performs rhetorically by casting the author in the same scientific lineage as the great evolutionary thinkers. Like Darwin and the geologist Charles Lyell, Wright will use historical evidence to examine trends in the evolution of civilization itself.
Through this discussion of evolution Wright leads to his second core point: that humans are, in fact, innately disposed to progress. Our predisposition to innovation is the reason we live in progress traps. As his coverage of early human evolution attempts to illustrate, we, just like our ancient ancestors, are programmed to expand, to overtake, and to use every new advancement we make as a step up to the next frontier of existence, even—or perhaps especially—at the expense of other species. The discussion and implicit equivocation of Victorian and early homo sapiens culture in a single chapter is an effective rhetorical tool, burlesquing Victorian society as just as primitive as cave-men.
In his discussion of Cro-Magnon man, Wright is guilty of playing somewhat fast-and-loose with human history. It is difficult to say whether Neanderthals and early humans were engaged in genocidal conflict, or whether this conflict caused innovations in tool and art creation. While an excellent teller of the story of humanity, Wright also tends to imaginatively reconstruct these narratives. This does not discredit his point that reading human history helps us understand the present, but it signals that his text requires careful reading for arguments that border on assumptions.